miércoles, 2 de abril de 2014

Debating an Eco-revolution

Debating an Eco-revolution
Dhruv Singhal


Global warming – man or myth?
If you look at information on global warming, there are millions of websites and scientific facts that tell us that global warming (or climate change) is well and truly real and is effecting and changing the lives of all people around the globe, as well as mass migration of animals and the damaging of crop cycles and many other momentous issues. However, there is an equal amount of research that claims that climate change is nothing but the overreaction of the end of the last ice age, to hit what is nowadays Europe around 5000 years ago. So, who do you believe? Why should we believe it? And is all this stuff on climate change and global warming all made so we are feared into buying new “eco-friendly” government funded projects? Therein lays the debate – which could go further as laws or government based decisions at any level.

Where to holiday? How about here! The rise of stay-cationing
The presumption that climate change is a real thing is a given in this debate, here we look at an interesting idea that has come out of the UK; the notion of a stay-cation. This idea basically works on people visiting other areas of their own country (staying at home) whilst treating it like a holiday (vacation), therefore offsetting CO2 levels for their flights, by staying and driving or walking to their holiday destinations, though is a really a good idea? The whole idea behind holidays is to relax, but do you still feel relaxed if you are holidaying in your own country? Or do you need the traditional sand, sea and sun holidays that are so frequent in Southern Europe? This is where people can pitch in ideas; it looks at each country on a touristic level, and whilst it could divide opinions on which is the best country to live and holiday in, it could allow people to finally appreciate the sights and sounds that they have of their own country. This debate, if successful would be used to talk to local governments to promote regional or national tourism, which could appeal to both the domestic and international tourist.


Are there any alternatives? Fossil fuel substitutes
This is a classic debate on climate change – which is the best alternative to gas and oil? Do we need to go to extreme lengths to get them too or is it as simple as solar panels in the south of the continent, wind turbines in the north and west and hydro-electricity and nuclear energy in the east? Or is it far more complicated that this? Many people would have many different views on this and it could cause a lively debate. Following the debate and a possible look to the EU legislation on alternative fuels this could be used to talk to national level governments about subsidies as well as incentives for people to use these new forms of energy.

Buy me growth – alternate energy gets us out of recession
This is purely for a business oriented idea, could the development/ research/ building and using of alternate energy services provide a new economy? The idea here is that with enough faith in the private sector of the 28 members of the EU could companies build, operate and utilize market principals to create growth, money for economies and most importantly jobs? This debate could be interesting as there are few sources out there that look at these sorts of issues and with the ability to talk to people all over Europe, whose individual country is at a different stage in its economic cycle – is investment in green energy the stimuli needed to get Europe back on track with a possible look at being world leaders in this sort of project. This can of course be combined with the idea above, and could be taken to regional, national or international levels of the political world with one eye on the Kyoto protocol which looks at more goals for EU and the rest of the UN nations by 2020.

Green vs Blue, which colour is better?
The use of green energy has always been around, it’s interesting, it’s safe, it’s everything we need right?  However, you can look at the alternatives, blue energy. This is the idea of an osmosis based work turning salt to fresh-water and using the salt to create energy? The only ideas behind this though are its cost and how well it works. It has an apparent efficiency rating of 91%, only nuclear power is more efficient but how well has it developed? There are already subsidies in place across the Netherlands and in Norway, but could it all take off? This debate can show an interesting step forward for Europe and has a good basis for Europe into the future. Along with these, it can be taken to any level of politics to be discussed further.

As shown there are many different options that are available to us to take on the renewable energy front, I feel it would be necessary to answer these questions and further build on the concept that is Eco revolution.

martes, 21 de mayo de 2013

El mapa y el territorio, de Michel Houellebecq


Es excesivamente narrativa a veces, a diferencia de las otras dos novelas que me he leído del autor ("Ampliación del campo de batalla", y "Las partículas elementales"), lo que no siempre se verifica en descripciones penetrantes o trascendentes. Las narraciones que hace se dedican en su mayoría a relatar encuentros insignificantes, superfluos, que pondrían a algún lector ávido no de acción pero sí de juicios cáusticos, a los que lo tiene acostumbrado Houellebecq, al borde apenas de la desesperación.
A primera vista, también, es menos políticamente incorrecta.

A primera vista, solamente. Porque a diferencia de "Ampliación..." y de "Las partículas...", es menos directo, menos panfletario, a la hora de señalar las debilidades, las enfermedades, los virus, que han infectado la civilización occidental; porque su tema sigue siendo la civilización, la civilización en los confines de la autodestrucción, del colapso, no por invasión, sino por la debilidad, por la falta de músculo. Houellebecq nos recuerda aquí al Lovecraft de "La calle"; Houellebecq parece ser consciente de la verdad expuesta por Jacob Burckhardt, otro visionario, y más bien profeta, de la decadencia occidental, que veía anunciada ya en el siglo XIX: "En la historia, la vía de la aniquilación es preparada de manera inmutable por la degeneración interna, por un decrecimiento de la vida. Solo entonces puede un estremecimiento externo ponerle un fin al todo"; verdad puesta ya en claro por otro profeta de la decadencia, esta vez en el siglo XIV, Ibn Khaldun: "A lo largo de la historia, muchas naciones han sufrido una derrota física. Pero cuando una nación es la víctima de una derrota sicológica, entonces eso marca el fin de una nación." Sicológico aquí quiere decir, claro, del alma, de la vocación, de la voluntad.

A primera vista, "El mapa y el territorio" puede ser simplemente una presentación de las formas que sustentan la civilización: la producción, el mantenimiento del orden, la satisfacción sexual. Sin embargo, es profundo, más profundo que en las obras mencionadas, al ser más sugerente, menos explícito, más insinuante, acerca del proceso como esos fundamentos se ven erosionados. Un cambio en el espíritu, una ausencia de percepción, una falta de conciencia colectiva, el mecanicismo de un sistema que anonada los esfuerzos por mantenerlo en funcionamiento.

Al final, el sistema productivo, el sistema sexual, el sistema del orden, dan paso a nuevas formas, que traerán consigo tal vez una nueva civilización, que no conocemos todavía plenamente, de la que el autor nos da unos brochazos, pero que tiene que representar de todos modos el hundimiento de la civilización en la que vivimos, y en la que hemos vivido desde el siglo XIX. El sistema industrial desaparece, el sistema del orden cambia, los técnicos toman el rol del investigador juicioso, representado por el Detective Jasselin y sus métodos anticuados para buscar la verdad, la pareja estable cede ante el avance de la liberación, de la dilución de la necesidad, y del galope inmarcesible, irrefrenable, despiadado, inexorable, de la liberación femenina. El individuo aquí pierde la conciencia, se torna un elemento más, el significado de su personalidad desaparece, sin nostalgia, sin pasado, sin futuro. Todo esto es puesto en las obras de arte ficticias de Jed Martin.

Al final, este desgranamiento, este desleimiento de nuestra cultura, con nuestros ojos fijos, inadaptables, solamente lo podemos ver como una recolonización de la naturaleza, como un "triunfo absoluto de la vegetación". Puede que sea menos directa esta novela, a primera vista es menos cáustica, pero retomando la narración y viéndola al trasluz de sus últimos dos párrafos, se comprende que Houellebecq pueda pertenecer sí, como él dice, al romanticismo, pero a un romanticismo decadentista, que pone el dedo en la llaga y aprieta fuerte.

domingo, 3 de junio de 2012

George Orwell. Antirracionalismo

George Orwell. Antirracionalismo
Tomado de 1984

"Al final, el Partido anunciaría que dos y dos son cinco y habría que creerlo. Era inevitable que llegara algún día al dos y dos son cinco. La lógica de su posición lo exigía. Su filosofía negaba no sólo la validez de la experiencia, sino que existiera la realidad externa. La mayor de las herejías era el sentido común. Y lo más terrible no era que le mataran a uno por pensar de otro modo, sino que pudieran tener razón. Porque, después de todo, ¿cómo sabemos que dos y dos son efectivamente cuatro? O que la fuerza de la gravedad existe. O que, el pasado no puede ser alterado. ¿Y si el pasado y el mundo exterior sólo existen en nuestra mente y, siendo la mente controlable, también puede controlarse el pasado y lo que llamamos la realidad?" 

"No has querido realizar el acto de sumisión que es el precio de la cordura. Has preferido ser un loco, una minoría de uno solo. Convéncete, Winston; solamente el espíritu disciplinado puede ver la realidad. Crees que la realidad es algo objetivo, externo, que existe por derecho propio. Crees también que la naturaleza de la realidad se demuestra por sí misma. Cuando te engañas a ti mismo pensando que ves algo, das por cierto que todos los demás están viendo lo mismo que tú. Pero te aseguro, Winston, que la realidad no es externa. La realidad existe en la mente humana y en ningún otro sitio. No en la mente individual, que puede cometer errores y que, en todo caso, perece pronto. Sólo la mente del Partido, que es colectiva e inmortal, puede captar la realidad. Lo que el Partido sostiene que es verdad es efectivamente verdad. Es imposible ver la realidad sino a través de los ojos del Partido. Éste es el hecho que tienes que volver a aprender, Winston. Para ello se necesita un acto de autodestrucción, un esfuerzo de la voluntad. Tienes que humillarte si quieres volverte cuerdo." 

"No destruimos a los herejes porque se nos resisten; mientras nos resisten no los destruimos. Los convertirnos, captamos su mente, los reformamos. Al hereje político le quitamos todo el mal y todas las ilusiones engañosas que lleva dentro; lo traemos a nuestro lado, no en apariencia, sino verdaderamente, en cuerpo y alma. Lo hacemos uno de nosotros antes de matarlo. Nos resulta intolerable que un pensamiento erróneo exista en alguna parte del mundo, por muy secreto e inocuo que pueda ser." 

"El poder es poder sobre seres humanos. Sobre el cuerpo, pero especialmente sobre la mente." 

"Controlarnos la materia porque controlamos la mente. La realidad está dentro del cráneo. Irás aprendiéndolo poco a poco, Winston. No hay nada que no podamos conseguir: la invisibilidad, la levitación... absolutamente todo. Si quisiera, podría flotar ahora sobre el suelo como una pompa de jabón. No lo deseo porque el Partido no lo desea. Debes librarte de esas ideas decimonónicas sobre las leyes de la Naturaleza. Somos nosotros quienes dictamos las leyes de la Naturaleza." 

"El poder consiste en derrumbar las mentes humanas en pedazos y en volver a juntarlas en nuevas formas según tu propia elección."

"Todo podía ser verdad. Las llamadas leyes de la Naturaleza eran tonterías. La ley de la gravedad era una imbecilidad."

lunes, 7 de mayo de 2012

Nicolás Gómez Dávila: "De iure" http://es.scribd.com/doc/92724890/Nicolas-Gomez-Davila-De-iure

martes, 17 de abril de 2012

Insight into 'The politics of Recognition' by Charles Taylor

Insight into 'The politics of Recognition' by Charles Taylor
by Dhruv Singhal
Charles Taylor plays with the Rosseauian idea that honor and hierarchy are interdependent as the other-dependent person is a slave to “opinion”, thus providing a critique for Pride (amour-propre). This renders humanity into a paradoxical condition where despite inequality in power, there exists dependence between the various strata of society. A perfectly balanced reciprocity of recognition on the other hand makes it compatible with liberty.
The importance of esteem is not to be disregarded, but for valuing a system of equality, reciprocity, and unity of purpose, for the defense of general will, all virtuous citizens are to be equally honored. Thus the age of dignity becomes existent. With reciprocated recognition among equal men, the problem of depravity of recognition is thus resolved.  The problem arises when the situation is analyzed from the perspective of differentiated purposes, which renders such reciprocated recognition impossible. If this difference in purposes is overlooked, a so called “homogenizing tyranny“ arises.
Some critics on the other hand choose to analyze recognition in a more negative light. Hegelian recognition is considered to have an inevitable aspect of hierachy characterized by domination of peoples over other.  According to Sartre, “our relations with other people are always conflictual as each of us attempts to negate the other in an intersubjective dual. The realisation of our own subjectivity is dependent upon our turning the other into an object. In turn, we are made to feel like an object within the gaze of the other.” Sartre further provides a crucial example which relates the shameful, objectifying experience of suddenly feeling the ‘look’ or ‘gaze’ of another person upon us when carrying out a contemptible act to the notion of mutual conflictual recognition. “In this moment of shame, I feel myself as an object and am thus denied existence as a subject. My only hope is to make the other into an object. There are no equal or stable relations between people; all interactions are processes of domination.” Levinas explores ethical issues regarding once methodology involved in ‘recognizing’ others. According to Levinas, “Hegelian recognition involves an unavoidable appropriation or assimilation of the other into one’s own subjectivity.” He posits that while recognizing others we inadvertently deem them knowable, fathomable, thus depriving them of the altered differences. He argues that this is infact the greatest ethical sin as one fails to recognize other in their full exteriority and the differences they might possess. “In effect, to recognize someone is to render them the same as us; to eliminate their inescapable, unapprehendable and absolute alterity.”
Paddy Queen from Queen’s University of Northern Island regards the inevitability of globalization and immigration, an important factor for the increased value of politics of recognition. In her own words, “Despite the criticism of the concept of recognition, there is an ever increasing value attached with recognition as a functional socio-political principle. The increasingly multicultural nature of societies throughout the world seems to call for a political theory which places respect for difference at its core. In this regard, recognition theories seem likely to only increase in influence. It should also be noted that they are very much in their infancy. It was only in the 1990s that theorists formulated a comprehensive account of recognition as a foundational concept within theories of justice. To this extent, they are still in the process of being fashioned and re-evaluated in the light of critical assessment from various schools of thought. For many thinkers, the concept of recognition captures a fundamental feature of human subjectivity. It draws attention to the vital importance of our social interactions in formulating our sense of identity and self-worth as well as revealing the underlying motivations for, and justifications of, political action. It seems particularly useful in making sense of notions of authenticity and the conditions for agency, as well as mapping out the conditions for rational responsibility and authority. As a result, recognition can be seen as an indispensable means for analyzing social movements, assessing claims for justice, thinking through issues of equality and difference, understanding our concrete relations to others, and explicating the nature of personal identity. Although there remain concerns regarding various aspects of recognition as a social and political concept, it is entirely possible that many of these will be addressed and resolved through future research.”
The question that Charles Taylor seeks to answer concerns the homogenizing effects of politics of equal dignity. He presents the Canadian case regarding the same, which involves a universal Charter of Rights applicable to all its citizens. It guarantees equal rights and treatment of all Canadians.
At it’s stake is the survival and autonomy of Quebec and aboriginal nations as distinct societies.
On the other hand there exists in self-governance and survival policies, like language laws to preserve different cultures. Special laws, for example, about language  exist (in order to ensure survival of francophone culture):
- Children of francophone or immigrant parents are not allowed to enter English schools.
- Businesses with more than 50 employees must be run in French.
- No advertisements in any other language than French.
They fear that their cultures -understood comprehensively as dynamically tensed and politicized articulations of way of life- will turn into the lifeless folklore of a museum diorama.
For a number of people in ‘English Canada’, a political society’s espousing certain collective goals threatens to run against both of these basic provisions of the Charter. The prominent reasons cited for this are:
1. Collective goals might put restrictions on the behavior of individuals that might violate their rights granted by the universal charter.
2. Espousing collective goals on behalf of a national group can be thought to be inherently discriminatory.
Dworkin’s liberalism considers two kinds of moral commitment: procedural and substantive. This implies that a liberal society cannot adopt a substantive view about the ends of life, aim to make people virtuous, because this would involve a violation of its procedural norm -it would not be treating the dissident minority with equal respect.
At the same time, a society with collective goals like Quebec’s violates this model as policies intended to facilitate survival seek to induce members of the community -not simply providing a facility to already existent people. Quebeckers therefore tend to opt for a different model of a liberal society.
This is achieved by distinguishing the fundamental liberties that should never be infringed from privileges and immunities that are important, but can be revoked or restricted for reasons of public policy.
There is a form of the politics of equal respect, which is enshrined in a liberalism of rights, that is inhospitable to difference, because (a) it insists on a uniform application of the rules defining these rights, without exception, and (b) it is suspicious of collective goals. Inhospitable because it cannot accommodate what the members of distinct societies really aspire to, which is survival.
Amelie Oksenberg Rorty argues, “But even if Taylor is permitted the accordion movement, expanding and contracting his definitions of culture and of language, he doesn’t provide an account of cultural differentiation. He focuses cultures as the immediate and proper objects of "the politics of recognition," he requires a criteria for distinguishing them that are narrower than the demarcation of natural languages and more precise than the differentiation of "ways of life." If cultures differ from other identity-defining groups by virtue of their solidarity and historical continuity, we need criteria for cohesive identity and continuity.
There are only few philosophers which consider themselves sensitive to the political aspects of apparently neutral philosophic issues than Charles Taylor. “By taking Quebec’s cultural survival as his primary example he has made his case easier for himself than it should be.” As Taylor presents them, the issues over Quebec’s recognition have focused almost exclusively on the preservation of a specific language and on the policies and institutions required for-and legitimated by-that preservation. With such a simplified and abstracted characterization of the constituents of culture, it is not too difficult to argue that liberalism can, without jeopardizing its primary commitments, extend certain rights of self-preservation to the dominant culture and to subcultures as long as the basic rights of individual citizens remain protected. But when cultures are more fully described, as including economic and political practices and attitudes, the politics of cultural definition and recognition becomes entangled in determining public policy on a vast range of substantive issues. For instance, how far might the preservation of Irish-American culture commit us to subsidizing the parochial schools of the Catholic population, recognizing that Catholic schools typically attempt to develop specific attitudes to many morally and politically charged divisive issues (publicly supported abortion, euthanasia, etc.) In funding parochial schools, does the state become an active party in determining not only their curricular standards, but also the direction of teaching?” Is it therefore necessary to assure that the day to day practices of such schools follow general anti-discrimination practices.
The paper revealed the struggle between equality and identity based justifications for affirmative action in liberal societies. It is a critique to the notion that liberalism is a possible meeting ground. It is on the other hand shown to be the political expression of one range of cultures, and quite incompatible with other ranges.
It has to be considered that all societies are becoming increasingly multicultural, while at the same time becoming more porous. There is, then, an intense vulnerability to personal relationships that has arisen from the collapse of honor and from the conflicting notions of what its substitute, recognition, can bestow. A new note has been struck in the history of friendship and marriage: that of desperation. For Taylor, this desperation comes from the inherently irresolvable tensions between conflicting views of human nature, each of which forms an indispensable foundation stone to contemporary liberal society:
“With the politics of equal dignity, what is established is meant to be universally the same, an identical basket of rights and immunities; with the politics of difference, what we are asked to recognize is the unique identity of this individual or group, their distinctness from everything else. The idea is that it is precisely this distinctness that has been ignored, glossed over, assimilated to a dominant or majority identity. And this assimilation is the cardinal sin against the ideal of authenticity.”
Hence he demands for recognition of equal value of different cultures. Decolonization of peoples and  a World of education. In all the debates about multiculturalism-about Afro-centered curricula, for example, or affirmative action, or perhaps above all, feminism-it is not sufficiently noted how inherently irresolvable this issue is when taken on its own terms. Society is being asked to provide two mutually contradictory supports to each individual: one based on his abstract humanity and the other on his unique particularity, and the two simply cannot be made to parse in the same political syntax, a point that Taylor, an Anglophone from Quebec, notes with rare acuity:
“These two modes of politics, then, both based on the notion of equal respect, come into conflict. For one, the principle of equal respect requires that we treat people in a difference-blind fashion. The fundamental intuition that humans command this respect focuses on what is the same in all. For the other, we have to recognize and even foster particularity. The reproach the first makes to the second is just that it violates the principle of nondiscrimination. The reproach the second makes to the first is that it negates identity by forcing people into a homogeneous mold that is untrue to them.”
Logic behind some of his demands seem to depend upon the premise that we owe equal respect to all cultures and there is something valid in this presumption, but the presumption is by no means unproblematic, e.g., not all art is of equal or even considerable value; every culture can go through phases of decadence.
It is to be noted that by explaining the right to identity as a need for original recognition, the tension between the tripartite justification of minority protection has disappeared. Consequently in the case of politics of societal differentiation, the three traditional justifications of minority rights are complementary: for if minorities are able to nurture their original recognition they will be able to take part in society on equal footing, without being or becoming identical to majority. Taking part in society on equal footing would mean being supported by a secure cultural structure, the minority feels that it has a voice outside the bounds of it’s own community.
The presumption should instead be thought of as a starting point. The very understanding of what it is to be of worth will be strange and unfamiliar to us. We require a “fusion of horizons” hosting the spectrums of cultures regardless of time.  Among the responses to Taylor's lecture, Michael Walzer's (the shortest) does remark on the hypocrisy behind Enlightenment liberalism ("no doubt state neutrality is often hypocritical, always incomplete"). Taylor, of course, does not characterize the Enlightenment/Romantic program as hypocrisy but rather as inherently contradictory, a point brought out, seemingly unconsciously, by Steven Rockefeller, another respondent, who juxtaposes these two sentences without appearing to notice how the one unravels the other:
“From the democratic perspective, particular cultures are critically evaluated in the light of the way they give distinct concrete expression to universal capacities and values. [Yet] the objective of a liberal democratic culture is to respect-not to repress-ethnic identities and to encourage different cultural traditions to develop fully their potential for expression of the democratic ideals of freedom and equality, leading in most cases to major cultural transformations.”
As Edward T. Oakes puts it, “But these transformations don't come cheap, which is precisely why the issue is so neuralgic. The contradiction lurking in all this rhetoric is the quite unspoken presupposition that governs this debate: that some culture has to be the chump and play the role of the fall guy, an admission that perhaps only comes to light in this telling line from respondent Susan Wolf: "And the problems of those who have been urged to ignore or suppress or remove their differences from white Christian heterosexuals can remind us of the dangers of trying to deny the significance, say, of gender differences that may run very deep." But what goes unrecognized in the book is how a Christian perspective on human nature might actually not only illuminate these difficulties but point a way, if not to their resolution, at least to an identification of their source. For example, one odd feature of the book is Taylor's assertion that the trend toward a politics of recognition can be seen as "just a continuation and development inaugurated by Saint Augustine, who saw the road to God as passing through our own self-awareness." What is insufficiently noted is how diametrically opposed are St. Augustine's view of human nature and that of Rousseau. Taylor at one point even quotes Rousseau to the effect that "with liberty, wherever abundance reigns, well-being also reigns"-scarcely, to say the least, a continuation of Augustine's pessimistic view of human nature. This Rousseauian optimism is perhaps the root of the modern pathos, for nothing could be so obviously self-refuting. In fact, it is out of the Rousseauian view of human nature that the politics of recognition first grew, and nothing more characterizes that politics than its sheer insatiability, as the German sidewalk streaker amply demonstrates.”

Sources
Paddy McQueen, 2011, Social and Political Recognition
Amelie Oksenberg Rorty, 1994, Political Theory, Sage Publications Inc.
Edward T. Oakes, 1993, Attention must be paid
F.F Mansvelt Beck,  Liberalism, Minorities & the politics of Societal Differentiation
Andreas Bucher, 2003, Ethnicity & State in Africa.

jueves, 23 de febrero de 2012

Nicolás Gómez Dávila: Decadence Derives from the Change of the Dominant Social Species

From: "Notas", 2003, Villegas, P. 265-266

A state, a city, are in decadence when their present dwellers belong to a social species different from that to which their creators belonged.
When the social predominance passes from one social species to another the phenomenon of decadence is produced, whatever it is the value attributed to the social species that succeeds in the posession of predominance.

jueves, 26 de enero de 2012

What's the deal with Megaupload?

What happened to Megaupload made me think some things. I want to share them with you. I speak about intellectual property, the legalization of extortion, and the return of the Luddites. All this involves an Orwellian scenario. It's 25 minutes. I hope you have the patience. Thanks!
First part, 15 min: http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=JAHYXsp_MRU
Second part: 10 min: http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=9VwkALjiRok